ON THE
IMPORTANCE OF BEING RADICAL
by John B. Cobb Jr
Is it bad to be “radical?” Often one hears the
statement that so-and-so is a “radical” as a reason not to pay attention to
what he or she says. To label people as “radicals” may be a way of warning
others that they are dangerous. It has much the same effect as calling them
“communists” or “terrorists.” This fear of radicals is not without reason. They
do propose new ideas that undercut some of those to which most people are attached.
They question the need for institutions and practices that others consider
essential and beneficial. From the point of view of those who are benefited by
the status quo and those who think
that things are going well, radicals are dangerous.
Rosa Parks, PHOTO: USIA |
When the modern period began in Europe, Christian
institutions and beliefs were very well established. A few brave modern people
raised radical questions that undercut the authority of Christian institutions
and the credibility of supernaturalist Christian teachings. Some of these
radicals paid dearly for their efforts. Christian institutions and beliefs did
not disappear, but they changed drastically. The change in their role in
Western societies has been even greater. The work of radicals has led to the
replacement of Christian societies by secular ones. Modern scientists were often in the lead in
advancing radicalism of this sort.
What is less noticed is that radicals are just as
threatening in other aspects of society. Political organizations, governments,
professions, academic disciplines, and educational institutions resist and
oppose their work just as religious communities often did. Sadly, this is true also
of modern sciences that profess to be fully open to evidence. In all these
contexts, radicals engage in just the questioning that is not wanted. While modern culture celebrates
the work of the radicals of earlier times, it is no more hospitable to
contemporary radicals than were the established leaders of those earlier
periods.
Many of us, at one time or another, have been
irritated by people raising questions of a theoretical nature in a group whose
job it is to deal practically with a problem. The zeal of radicals to go deeper
simply slows us down in getting our work done. Not all radicals have good
judgment about when and where to raise their questions, and for many people the
answer to the question of when and where radicals should seek attention is: never
and nowhere. It is easy to understand and even sympathize with those who abhor
radicals.
But modern society has needed radicals as much as earlier. A century ago a few voices were pointing out that
American society was rooted in racism and sexism. The vast majority of
Americans dismissed such talk as “radical” and therefore irrelevant. They were
right that it was radical. But these radical voices finally forced themselves
into the public consciousness. More and more people recognized that the call
for radical change had truth and righteousness on its side. There is still a
lot of racism and sexism in American society, but they are no longer supported
by law and official thinking. The work of radicals has changed society
radically. Even many who were once irritated and even angered by them are now
grateful for their work. Today the most glaring problems in American society
are economic. Accordingly, this is the area most in need of radical
investigation. We need radicals to go to the roots of these problems. This
could lead us in a variety of directions. The financial sector now dominates
the economy; so we could focus on how this has gained so much power. The
increase in inequality in the distribution of income and wealth has grown very
rapidly. Radicals ask for the deepest reasons for this development.
Some of the reasons that radicals will find are
grounded in political power and personal acquisitiveness. But there are
strictly theoretical contributions to these evils. There is a good deal of synchronicity
between economic teaching and governmental and global practice. Accordingly,
one place to apply radical analysis is the dominant economic theory.
Let’s take a simple example. The discipline of
economics is founded on the assumption that bigger is better. It is supposed
that the more economic activity takes place, the better off people are. Economists
take their role to be showing how to make the economy grow. From time to time
radicals have asked whether growth is the right goal for the economy, but
within the academic departments of philosophy, the question has not been
seriously discussed. Those who have tried to do so have not been well treated.
Asking that question is threatening to the discipline of economics as it has long been constituted. On the other hand, failing to ask it out of respect for the current authorities has the same kind of effect as failing to ask about racism or sexism out of respect for the existing authorities of an earlier day. The global growth of economic activity on a finite planet is responsible for such serious problems as global warming. If the economics guild continues to silence those of its members who raise this question because it is “radical,” the danger to human life is increased.
Asking that question is threatening to the discipline of economics as it has long been constituted. On the other hand, failing to ask it out of respect for the current authorities has the same kind of effect as failing to ask about racism or sexism out of respect for the existing authorities of an earlier day. The global growth of economic activity on a finite planet is responsible for such serious problems as global warming. If the economics guild continues to silence those of its members who raise this question because it is “radical,” the danger to human life is increased.
The crucial question is simple, but radical. Is growth
a final good in itself? Or is it good only insofar as it improves the human
condition? If the latter, should we not investigate how the increase of
economic activity, guided by the principles of standard economics, is actually
affecting the human condition? That is a “radical” thing to do. It is also
empirical.
To be empirical is to pay close attention to the
facts. That is, itself, a “radical” thing to do. In some cases, the facts will
not support the patterns of thought of many people, perhaps not those of any of
us. Science at its best calls on us to accept the facts even when we wish they
were otherwise. For example, many people prefer to think we are fundamentally
disconnected from all other living things and, for a long time, science
supported that idea. But the evidence for evolution became overwhelming. However
unsettling the truth may be, it remains the truth, and many of us hold to the
radical idea that we should affirm the truth and adjust our way of thinking to
it.
"Galapagos Islands" PHOTO: Michael R. Perry |
I have spoken of “science at its best.” Sadly, science
is not always at its best. Modern scientists like to point to one particularly
dramatic example of failure at this point: the case of Galileo. It is often
presented as an instance of science vs. religion, but it was in fact a matter
of a new development in science that opposed the scientific consensus of its
day. The church supported this consensus.
The best science of the medieval period was based on
Aristotle. The church shared the scientists’ respect for Aristotle. Aristotle
thought that heavenly bodies were fundamentally different from the Earth. The
scientists who followed him were persuaded by his arguments. Galileo used a new
technology to introduce evidence that did not fit into this understanding of
the universe. The scientists who represented the scientific consensus of that
day refused even to look through the telescope. They wanted to silence
Galileo’s radical challenge to established science. Modern scientists have liked
to condemn the resistance of late medieval Aristotelian scientists to the
evidence provided by Galileo. They often imply that this was a failing of medieval
scientists that modern science overcame. Sad to say, modern scientists engage
in the same kind of practice even today. They strongly resist attending to
evidence that does not fit into their worldview. To point this out is to be a
“radical.”
For example, most modern scientists are committed to a
worldview in which events in the physical world can be affected only by other
events in the physical world. There is an enormous amount of evidence that
physical events are in fact affected by what happens in human subjective
experience. That my hands type one set of words rather than another certainly
seems to be affected by my thinking. That mental activity plays a role in
bodily behavior is not only common sense but also has an immense amount of evidence
in its favor. But the metaphysics with which modern science is closely
associated says that it is impossible. Accordingly, such affirmations are
rejected by most scientific guilds as impossible. Most scientists refuse to look at the evidence. This
exclusion of a great amount of evidence is not science at its best.
Asking science to open itself to evidence that does
not fit into its worldview is a radical act. It is as difficult for modern
scientists to do this as for Aristotelian scientists to accept the evidence
provided by Galileo. One reason for this difficulty is the commitment of
scientists to what they call “empiricism.” This empiricism was shaped by
philosophers and scientists in the early modern period. It affirmed the view
that the only access to the world external to the individual thinker is through
the sense organs. For practical purposes, scientists and philosophers limited
themselves to what could be seen or touched. We can call the resulting idea
about how we know anything about the world “sensory empiricism.” Scientists found
that it was possible to agree on a great many things when they limited
themselves in this way. They celebrated the “objectivity” of science. They
often identify “science” as such with the body of theory that developed out of
sensory empiricism.
This magazine is certainly committed to “empiricism,”
in the broad meaning of this term. We must begin all our reflections in
experience. In order to explain our experience, we may have to posit some
things we do not experience. Indeed science does this in spades. These days
scientists tell us that most matter and most energy can never be experienced at
all. They call them “dark.” But these theories, and all our theories, should be
tested again and again in experience.
There is no question of the crucial importance of
experience. However, we need to ask more radically about it. When we do so, we
find that it includes much more than the deliverances of the sense organs. In
fact scientists have to assume a great deal that they cannot derive from sense
experience.
I limit myself to one example. Much of science is
engaged in explaining how things come to be through time. Causality is usually
understood as the impact of the past upon the present. But vision and touch
give us only the present. Of course, we assume that we see things following one
upon another. But that assumption requires something other than the immediate
delivery of visual or tactile experience. We have to remember the previous visual experience in order to see that there
is a change or motion.
If this point is not immediately clear, take a little
time to think about it. Focus on what you are seeing in a single moment. It
will be a complex pattern of colors. Now you are very likely to think that you
see changes taking place. But if you limit yourself entirely to what is given
you through your eyes this is not quite true. In the new moment you are seeing
a slightly different pattern of color, but you are no longer seeing the
previous one. Without memory, you cannot compare them. You do not see the
change. We do not see or touch memory.
Puzzles of this kind have long been formulated by
philosophers but they have rarely been taken seriously by scientists. If one
does take them seriously, one is pushed to a more “radical” empiricism, one
that examines experience as a whole with greater care and sees the
interrelationships of its ingredients. William James contributed this term:
“radical empiricism.” Our actual experience is one of constant change. It is
not wrong for science to talk about changes in the world based on experience. What
is wrong is to claim to limit itself to the objective world as known only
through sight and touch. Science does not do this. It cannot do this. Unfortunately,
it does not attend to the contribution of other aspects of experience, and it gives
support to a very truncated view of reality.
Those who build their understanding of reality on what
contemporary science offers tend to devalue value. The reality of our
experience is that it is profoundly value-laden. We have hope and fear,
satisfaction and dissatisfaction, enjoyment and misery, and so much more. We
are constantly involved in questions of better and worse. Scientists may
acknowledge that such feelings occur, but modern scientific orthodoxy insists
that they have no effect upon the world. The world is value free, and science
is supposed to be value free. Now research universities are supposed to be
value free as well – which means that their only value is money.
Radical empiricism is another matter. For it, feelings,
beliefs, sensory experiences, memories, anticipations, bodily experience, and
intellectual activity are all equally real and very much bound up together. We
can, of course, abstract certain sensory experiences from this whole and
concentrate upon them. Much can be learned in this way. But when this limited
aspect of knowledge is given special privilege and all the rest is disparaged,
we are in serious trouble.
The real world, the world of the radical empiricist,
is much richer. It calls forth concern and commitment as the purely “objective”
world does not. It opens us to fresh approaches in economics and in physics,
and in everything else as well.
Earlier I mentioned the overwhelming evidence that
evolution has taken place and that the human species emerged through
evolutionary processes. But radical empiricism opens us to an understanding of
evolution quite different from the one to which sensory empiricism, with its
purely objective world, has led us. One example is the explanation of the
emergence of new species. Standard academic teaching that fits the narrowly
scientific worldview is that all the variations in plants and animals among
which natural selection operates are caused by random mutation of genes. Lynn
Margulis disagreed, saying that at least some of them occurred by
symbiogenesis, that is, by diverse organisms combining. She gave as her most
important example the emergence of the nucleated cell. She said this did not
come about by random mutation of genes but by one bacterium swallowing another
and not digesting it. Her idea was long rejected, even ridiculed, because it
did not fit the standard model. But the evidence finally forced its acceptance.
Sadly, despite this important realization, and even though Margulis provided
evidence of the role of symbiogenesis elsewhere as well, the standard account
of evolution has not been modified to make a place for it. Radical empiricists, in contrast, are completely open to the
evidence.
More broadly there is a great deal of evidence that
purposive actions on the part of animals, especially human beings, play a large
role in evolution. But mainstream evolutionary theory ignores the effects of the
action of animals on evolution because this would give an opening to
acknowledging a role for some sort of purpose in evolution.
The exclusion of purpose from evolutionary theory is
one of its sacred principles. We find evolutionary biologists vigorously
denying that purpose plays any role in the world for the purpose of maintaining
ideas that do not have empirical support. Radical empiricists
do not see why we should ignore the evidence for the role of the purposes of
the evolving animals, especially human beings.
Late Medieval science allied itself with Aristotelian
philosophy and gave much too large a role to purpose. Modern philosophy allied
itself with materialism and denied purpose altogether. Wouldn’t it be better
for science to pay attention to the evidence, all the evidence, instead of being enthralled by its companion
philosophy? Let’s join radical empiricists and this magazine in the truly
open-ended quest for truth.
PHOTO: Harley Pebley |
This article appeared in the July 2012 issue of Empirical. John Cobb followed this up with an article entitled "The Resurgence of Purpose" in the August 2012 issue, which is now at bookstores near you, and can be ordered online as well. Our September 2012 issue will feature yet another article by John Cobb that is called "The Resurrection of God." The article on purpose is a discussion of the dismissal of modern science, and its "resurgence" in recent science. The resurrection article follows up on this from a theological standpoint.
ReplyDelete